The Idea Of The Historical Buddha1
David Drewes
Journal of the International Association of Buddhist Studies Volume 40 âą 2017 âą 1â25 âą doi: 10.2143/JIABS.40.0.3269003
Abstract
This paper discusses and reevaluates the idea of the historical Buddha. Focusing on a survey of nineteenth and twentieth-century scholarship, it argues that the Buddhaâs historicity was never actually established and that he cannot properly be regarded as a historical figure.
Article
The idea of the historical Buddha is one of the most basic and familiar in the field of Buddhist studies, but also one of the most confusing and problematic. On one hand, the Buddha is universally agreed to have lived; but, on the other, more than two centuries of scholarship have failed to establish anything about him. We are thus left with the rather strange proposition that Buddhism was founded by a historical figure who has not been linked to any historical facts, an idea that would seem decidedly unempirical, and only dubiously coherent. Stuck in this awkward situation, scholars have rarely been able to avoid the temptation to offer some suggestion as to what was likely, or âmustâ have been, true about him. By the time they get done, we end up with a flesh and blood person - widely considered to be one of the greatest human beings ever to have lived - conjured up from little more than fancy. Here I would like to try to shed some light on this problem by reviewing the scholarship that introduced and sustained the idea of the historical Buddha. Though several valuable studies of this work have already appeared, they generally depict the process as one of progressive, ultimately successful, discovery. What I will try to suggest is that, if we pay close attention, it turns out that no discovery was actually made, and that no basis for treating the Buddha as a historical figure has yet been identified.
Although the Western encounter with Buddhism goes back centuries, in the first decades of the nineteenth century, hardly anything was actually known, and the question of Buddhismâs origin remained completely open. Many authors felt comfortable treating the Buddha as historical, but opinions varied widely. The idea that the Buddha was from Africa, proposed by Engelbert Kaempfer in the early eighteenth century, retained sufficient currency that Jean-Pierre Abel-RĂ©musat, the leading French authority, devoted an article to refuting it in 1819. 2 In 1823, Julius Klaproth argued against the still popular identification of the Buddha and the Norse god Odin, which had been proposed by William Jones in 1788. 3 In 1825, Horace Hayman Wilson, arguably the leading British authority, proposed a version of the so-called two-Buddha theory, according to which there was an elder Buddha who lived between the tenth and twelfth centuries B.C.E., and a younger one who lived in the sixth or seventh. He also suggested that Buddhism may have been brought to India from Central Asia. 4 At the highest level of scholarship, the Buddhaâs historicity was regarded as something that remained to be established. RĂ©musat, though sympathetic to the idea that the Buddha was historical, suggested in his 1819 article that it was necessary to avoid âprejudging the question one could raise on the reality of the historical existence of the figure called Buddha.â 5 In his 1819 Sanskrit dictionary, Wilson defined ĆÄkyamuni as âthe real or supposed founder of the Baudâdha [i.e., Buddhist] religionâ (s.v.). In 1827 Henry Colebrooke, the other leading British authority, similarly referred to the Buddha noncommittally as the âreputed author of the sĂștrasâ (558).
The development that began to focus scholarly inquiry was Brian Houghton Hodgsonâs discovery of Sanskrit Buddhist manuscripts in Nepal in 1822, which he first discussed in print in 1828. 6 Recent scholarship has focused mainly on the fact that Hodgson sent shipments of these manuscripts to EugĂšne Burnouf, who used them as the basis for his Introduction Ă lâhistoire du bouddhisme indien, published in 1844, which some have considered the main publication that established the Buddha as a historical figure. As we shall see, however, the actual argument Burnouf makes is not based on anything he found in Hodgsonâs texts, but on two facts that Hodgson himself reported in 1828, which occupied scholarly discussion through the 1830s: first, that Nepalese texts report that Buddhism was revealed consecutively, over a period of aeons, by seven Buddhas: VipaĆyin, Ćikhin, ViĆvabhĆ«, Krakucchanda, Kanakamuni, KÄĆyapa, and ĆÄkyamuni; and, second, that these texts claim to preserve the teachings of ĆÄkyamuni, but not those of any of the earlier Buddhas. 7
Versions of the tradition of former Buddhas had already been reported by several authors, going back to at least the seventeenth century, but the fact that it was found in Hodgsonâs Sanskrit texts, which were presumed to be significantly older and more authentic than anything previously available, pushed it to the fore as the central piece of evidence on Buddhismâs origin. Hodgson tentatively treated the tradition as historical, writing that âit has not occurred to me at present to doubt the historical existence of SĂĄkyaâs six predecessorsâ; âSĂĄkya is the last of the seven genuine Buddhas.â Trying to make sense of why Buddhist scriptures depict ĆÄkyamuni, but not any of the other Buddhas, as their speaker, he suggested that ĆÄkyamuni was âto Buddhism what VyĂĄsa [was] to Brahmanism,â in that he âcollected and secured ⊠the doctrines taught by his predecessors, and himself.â 8 Wilson, maintaining the suspicion he expressed in his Sanskrit dictionary, and evidently having given up his two-Buddha theory, was more skeptical, suggesting in an article published in the same issue of the same journal, of which he was the editor, that it is âvery questionableâ âhow many of these Buddhas are real personagesâ and that âSĂĄkya, as identifiable with Gautama, was, possibly, the founder of the Bauddha system as it now existsâ (1828: 455-456). Addressing the specific question of Gautama Buddha in an 1832 article, he again suggested that he could be either âhistorical or fictitiousâ (1832b: 256).
Having apparently moved past the doubts expressed in his 1819 article, RĂ©musat had suggested in 1821 that the Wakan sansai zue, an early eight-eenth-century Japanese encyclopedia that provided dates for each of the so-called Chan patriarchs going back to the Buddha, could make it possible to date ĆÄkyamuniâs death to 950 ĐČ.C.E. (9). When Hodgsonâs initial notices appeared, RĂ©musat took a strong interest in the former Buddhas and addressed the issue in several publications before his untimely death in 1832. In one, he suggests that there may have been a âfew men who preceded [the Buddha] in the career of deificationâ and in another he simply repeats Hodgsonâs suggestion that the Buddha was the last of the seven human Buddhas and that he was like Buddhismâs VyÄsa. 9 In his translation of Faxianâs Fo guo ji, published posthumously in 1836, he shifts perspective and suggests that ĆÄkyamuni was âthe sole real type after whom, according to general belief, these imaginary personages [i.e., the previous Buddhas] were created by an afterthought, and referred to mythological times.â 10
In his First Twenty Chapters of the Mahawanso, George Turnour, the leading British scholar in what is now Sri Lanka, argued that a basic distinction could be drawn between Gautama and the Buddhas who preceded him. Pointing out that, according to Buddhist belief, before a Buddha arises in the world, ânot only does the religion of each preceding [Buddha] become extinct, but the recollection and record of all preceding events are also lost,â he suggested that âby this fortunate fiction, a limitation has been made to the mystification in which the buddhistical creed has involved all the historical data, contained in its literature, anterior to the advent of GĂłtomo.â Buddhist traditions about the first six Buddhas âare based on his revelation,â and can thus be ignored as likely mythical, but traditions concerning Gautama himself, qua revealer, can be treated as historical. Though the stories of Gautama and his disciples possess âglaring absurdities and gross superstitions,â Turnour argued, âthese defects ⊠in no degree prejudiceâ the data they contain âin as far as they subserve the ⊠ends of history.â 11 Although this was an elegant solution, Turnour continued to have doubts. In his âPĂĄli Buddhistical Annals,â published serially in the Journal of the Asiatic Society of Bengal in 1837 and 1838 , he suggested that it might be possible to decide the important question of whether or not KÄĆyapa Buddha, and perhaps some of the other Buddhas before him, were historical with evidence from nonBuddhist texts (1838: 687). In 1836, Turnourâs associate, Jonathan Forbes, contributed an article to the same journal in which he tried to establish dates for each of the last four Buddhas, suggesting 3101 ĐČ.C.E. for the death of Krakucchanda, 2099 for Kanakamuni, 1014 for KÄĆyapa, and 543 for Gautama. 12 In an essay written in the mid-thirties and published as an appendix to Forbesâs 1840 Eleven Years in Ceylon, Turnour commented that âin the course of his inquiries into the portion of the history of Ceylon ⊠connected with the Budhas of this [kalpa], who preceded Gautama (which I left wholly untouched), [Forbes] has ascertained that many satisfactory data ⊠may yet be gleaned from the native annals.â 13
While Burnoufâs 1844 Introduction has received significant attention in recent years, with renewed interest resulting from Donald Lopezâs studies and co-translation, with Katia Buffetrille, of the text into English, so far as I am aware no one has yet discussed the actual argument he makes for the Buddhaâs historicity. Because it is so closely bound up with the question of the previous Buddhas, it has perhaps been easy to overlook:
I have attributed the origin of these books to ĆÄkyamuni, that is to say, to the last of the seven human buddhas whose memory the tradition has preserved. On this point I have only reproduced the opinion of the Nepalese, who attribute the composition or the redaction of their sacred books to the last of the buddhas they recognize. The date of these books is thus placed in historical time and is shielded from all uncertainties and all doubts that could arise if the tradition had linked it to the existence of this or that of the ancient buddhas who, if they ever existed, will escape the grasp of the historical critic for a long time to come⊠It is ⊠an advantage to be spared from having to examine ⊠the question of knowing when the six buddhas who, so to speak, preceded ĆÄkyamuni existed, or from having to demonstrate, as capable critics think, that these buddhas owe their existence to the desire that the last one would have had to ensure for his doctrine the merit of a tradition consecrated by a long series of ancient sages⊠I do not wish to say by this that we have to reject ⊠everything that the Buddhist books recount about these buddhas previous to ĆÄkya⊠I wish solely to establish that the question of the origin of the Buddhist books must remain separate from that of the ancient buddhas; and I wish to record, in the name of the critic, the testimony of the Nepalese, which does not permit tracing back beyond the last buddha any of the works that have preserved the Buddhist doctrines for us. 14
Rather than presenting a new discovery or argument based on his study of Hodgsonâs texts, Burnouf continues the speculation on the seven Buddhas that had occupied scholars for the past decade and a half. Indeed, the great scholar seems to have little to add to the discussion. The idea that the tradition of the previous Buddhas represents an attempt to project Buddhist tradition into mythical antiquity had already been suggested by RĂ©musat. 15 The idea that Buddhist textsâ identification of ĆÄkyamuni or Gautama, rather than any of the previous Buddhas, as their speaker separates the question of his historicity from theirs would seem to be borrowed from Turnour. In defense of the central point of treating ĆÄkyamuni as historical, which RĂ©musat and Turnour glossed over, Burnouf states somewhat anticlimactically that he has merely âreproduced the opinion of the Nepalese,â presenting traditional belief as historical fact. On the basis of the materials he had, Burnouf could equally well have opined that the Buddha was ahistorical, or that the matter remained undecided. His depiction of the Buddha as a historical figure represented no more than his preferred opinion.
In the years following Burnoufâs work, concern for the previous Buddhas faded into the background and scholarly focus shifted to the final Buddha. Burnoufâs presentation of Indian Buddhism so far eclipsed everything that had appeared before it that some were willing to accept the Buddhaâs historicity on his authority. Wilson, however, famously remained unconvinced. In his âOn Buddha and Buddhism,â delivered in 1854 and published in 1856, he lauded Burnoufâs accomplishments but expressed serious reservations about the Buddhaâs historicity. 16 He suggested that while âit does not seem improbable that an individual ⊠should have set up a school of his own in opposition to the Brahmanical monopoly ⊠about six centuries before Christâ it is nevertheless âvery problematical whether any such person as SĂĄkya Sinha, or SĂĄkya Muni, or Sramana Gautama, ever actually existed.â He also suggested that âit seems not impossible, after all, that SĂĄkya Muni is an unreal being, and that all that is related of him is as much a fiction as is that of his preceding migrations, and the miracles that attended his birth, his life, and his departureâ (Wilson 1856: 247-248). While Wilsonâs perspective is now generally treated as an example of extreme skepticism, no one had yet brought anything to light to assuage the doubts he had been expressing for almost the past forty years. Wilsonâs own, somewhat more prosaic, suggestion was that the emergence of Buddhism could be attributed to âa person, or what is more likely, persons of various castes,â about whom we know little or nothing (248).
In the first volume of his Die Religion des Buddha, published in 1857, Carl Friedrich Koeppen explicitly rejected Wilsonâs doubts and made a novel attempt to establish the Buddhaâs existence by an a priori route, suggesting that evidence was not necessary. Presenting an early version of what would become one of the main arguments for the Buddhaâs historicity, he argued that âthe emergence of an order, a sect, a church without a founder is inconceivable, and it is almost as inconceivable that the memory of this founder could ever go completely out in the circle of his followers and adherentsâ (1857: 73). Robert Spence Hardy, who in 1850 and 1853 published two of the dayâs most influential monographs advocating the idea of the historical Buddha, took Wilsonâs criticisms to heart. In his 1866 Legends and Theories of the Buddhists, he quotes Wilsonâs article at length and softens his own stance considerably, suggesting that âneither the age, nor even the individual existence, of Buddha, is established beyond all controversy.â 17 In his Christianity and Buddhism Compared, published posthumously in 1874, he seems to give up the notion of the historical Buddha almost completely, suggesting that the Buddha is âa creature of the imagination alone, though formed, it may be, from the glimmerings of true tradition ⊠a phantom formed from the brain of ascetics ⊠who note down dreams and attaching to them names, call their records history.â 18
In his 1857 Buddhism and Buddhist Pilgrims, Max MĂŒller treats Wilsonâs doubts as legitimate, writing that âwe know little ⊠of [Buddhismâs] first origin and spreading, because the canonical works on which we must chiefly rely for information belong to a much later period, and are strongly tinged with a legendary character. The very existence of such a being as Buddha ⊠has been doubted. But what can never be doubted is ⊠that Buddhism ⊠had its origin in Indiaâ (1857: 4-5). In his article âBuddhism,â published in 1862, two years after Wilsonâs death, however, he discusses and dismisses Wilsonâs concerns, and claims, without citing any evidence or reason, that âwe may be satisfied that Buddhism ⊠had a real founderâ and that âwe have only to look at the works on ancient philosophy and religion published some thirty years ago, in order to perceive the immense progress that has been made in establishing the true historical character of the founder of Buddhismâ (MĂŒller [1862] 1867: 217-219, 222). Ămile Senart famously argued in his Essai sur la lĂ©gende du Buddha, published serially between 1873 and 1875, that the legend of the Buddha was a solar myth, and Hendrik Kern presented a similar theory in his monumental Geschiedenis van het Buddhisme in IndiĂ«, published between 1882 and 1884. 19
Overall, leading scholars in the decades following the publication of Burnoufâs work remained profoundly vexed by the question of the Buddhaâs existence. The idea of the historical Buddha seemed realistic and made it possible to depict Buddhism in an interesting way, but many, perhaps most, leading scholars felt restrained by the lack of evidence. Over the preceding decades, scholars had penetrated the mists of time, traced the origin of Buddhism to India, located Buddhist scriptures, and discovered that they claimed to have been taught by an omniscient, or nearly omniscient, supernatural human, or semi-human, being. But this was the end of the road. Committing to a euhemerist interpretation of this supernatural Buddha, the only sort of Buddha known to even the earliest texts, required scholars to make a resolute leap beyond the point where the facts could take them. Defending his treatment of the Buddha as historical in his 1853 Manual of Budhism, Hardy quotes Barthold Niebuhr as stating that âunless a boldness of divination, liable as it is to abuse, be permitted, all researches into the earlier history of nations must be abandonedâ (139). Some scholars were willing to take part in this bold divination; others were not.
The two main scholars who established the Buddhaâs historicity in scholarship were T.W. Rhys Davids and Hermann Oldenberg. Both focused on Pali texts, which had come to be generally accepted as older than Hodgsonâs Sanskrit texts, and used them to work up exciting depictions of the Buddhaâs life and teaching. Rather than using their texts to justify treating the Buddha as historical, however, they took the Buddhaâs historicity as a premise and used it as the basis for interpreting their texts as historical records. Though many found their presentations compelling, this approach left both scholars unable to respond to doubts about the Buddhaâs historicity in more than somewhat embarrassing ways. In his influential 1878 Encyclopadia Britannica article âBuddhism,â Rhys Davids comments:
As late as the year 1854 the late Professor Wilson of Oxford read a paper before the Royal Asiatic Society of London in which he maintained that the supposed life of Buddha was a myth, and âBuddha himself merely an imaginary being.â No one, however, would now support this view; and it is admitted that, under the mass of miraculous tales which have been handed down regarding him, there is a basis of truth already sufficiently clear to render possible an intelligible history. 20
Two things are noteworthy here. First, Rhys Davids, the dayâs leading advocate of the idea of the historical Buddha, presents nothing more robust than an ad populum argument: We know that the Buddha lived because people accept that he did. Second, however, his claim that scholars agreed that the legends preserve a âbasis of truth ⊠sufficiently clear to render possible an intelligible historyâ was not true. Though Wilson and Hardy had died, the latterâs Christianity and Buddhism Compared and Senartâs Essai sur la lĂ©gende du Buddha had just been published, and Kern would publish his Geschiedenis, where, like Senart, he would depict the Buddha as a myth, a few years later. 21
Though Oldenberg presents an in-depth discussion of the details of the legend of the Buddha, on the central question of his historical existence, in the first edition of his seminal Buddha: Sein Leben, seine Lehre, seine Gemeinde, published in 1881, when he was only twenty-six years old, he does no more than reiterate Koeppenâs claim that evidence is unnecessary, stating that âBuddhism must have had a founderâ and that the Buddhaâs âreality ⊠is a logical necessity [ein logisches Postulat], inasmuch as we see the reality of the Church founded by him.â 22 Though such reasoning may seem strange today, Oldenberg wrote during the heyday of the Great Man theory, which envisioned individual, heroic men as being responsible for all of the main developments in history. We see an amplified version of the same idea in Monier Monier-Williamsâ Buddhism, published at the end of the decade:
Buddhism is nothing without Buddha⊠No religion or religious system which has not emanated from some one heroic central personality, or in other words, which has not had a founder whose strongly marked personal character constituted the very life and soul of his teaching and the chief factor in its effectiveness, has ever had any chance of achieving world-wide acceptance, or ever spread far beyond the place of its origin (1889: 18).
In the second and third editions of his great work, apparently finding Rhys Davidsâ strategy preferable, Oldenberg omits his claim about the logical necessity of the Buddhaâs existence and instead asserts merely that it âcurrently seems generally acceptedâ that stories of the Buddhaâs life contain historical records (1890: 74, 1897: 82). In the three subsequent editions published during his life, and the seventh, published posthumously, but containing an appendix with his final revisions, Oldenberg does not present any explicit argument for the Buddhaâs historicity, perhaps having concluded that it was no longer necessary. 23
Such is the work that established the Buddhaâs historical existence. From roughly this time, the Buddhaâs historicity has been regarded as settled fact, and scholarship on the Buddha has primarily involved attempts to determine what the available sources might be able to tell us about his life, teaching, and date. Despite the often impressive erudition that has gone into this work, however, it has not done anything to strengthen the initial presupposition of the Buddhaâs existence. If one presupposes that Agamemnon was historical, one can spend oneâs life sifting through the legends for potential evidence about him; if one does not, the effort is meaningless. In rare cases in which leading scholars have returned to the root question, they have continued to rely on versions of the nineteenth-century arguments we have already considered. We see this, for instance, in the work of arguably the three most influential twentieth-century advocates of the idea of historical Buddha in Western scholarship: E.J. Thomas, Ătienne Lamotte, and AndrĂ© Bareau.
In his 1927 Life of Buddha as Legend and History, Thomas presented the most in-depth analysis of the legends of the Buddhaâs life published to that date. Though he believed firmly in the historical Buddha, he doubted whether any historical data could be located in the sources, and suggested that âhistorical criticismâ is insufficient to âextract the thread of a credible storyâ (227). Addressing the question of the Buddhaâs historicity, he quotes Wilsonâs old suggestion that the Buddha may have been an âunreal beingâ and writes:
In the following pages an attempt will be made to distinguish the earliest accounts, but this does not touch the fundamental question. Is there a historical basis at all? It must be remembered that some recognised scholars have denied and still deny that the story of Buddha contains any record of historical events. We further have the undoubted fact that various well-known characters once accepted as historical are now consigned to legendary fiction, such as Dido of Carthage, Prester John, Pope Joan, and Sir John Mandeville. The reply to those who would treat Buddha in the same way is not to offer a series of syllogisms, and say, therefore the historical character is proved. The opponents must be challenged to produce a theory more credible⊠An indolent scepticism which will not take the trouble to offer some hypothesis more credible than the view which it discards does not come within the range of serious discussion (Thomas 1927: xvii-xviii).
For Thomas, rather than something that has been or can be proved, the existence of the historical Buddha is simply a realistic hypothesis. Though he suggests that we must accept this hypothesis unless we can provide a better one, a third option would simply be to acknowledge that we do not know how Buddhism originated. Later in the text, Thomas addresses the views of R. Otto Franke, perhaps the last noteworthy defender of Wilsonâs views, quoting his assertion that ânaturally somebody (or somebodies) has (or have) created it, otherwise it would not be there. But who this somebody was, and whether there were not rather several somebodies, we have no knowledge.â Thomas replies simply that âthis however is not the generally accepted view, and for it to be accepted it would be necessary to go on and show that the theory that the records are all inventions ⊠is the more credible view. 24 Restating Rhys Davidsâ old ad populum argument, he adds only the somewhat strange suggestion that the Buddhaâs historicity is somehow supported by âthe records,â when in his own analysis he does not identify anything that he considers a record of historical fact.
Lamotte and Bareauâs extensive studies, published a few decades later, represented a significant advance on Thomasâ work and remain standard today. Though Lamotte insisted strongly on the Buddhaâs historicity, he concluded that isolating a core of historical fact from the various texts was impossible and that any attempt to do so would be âuseless, and harmful to researchâ (1947: 48). Having found nothing that he thought could be presented as evidence, he ended up relying on a strong version of the old Great Man theory of Koeppen, Oldenberg, and MonierWilliams. In his 1958 Histoire du bouddhisme indien, he writes that âBuddhism could not be explained unless we accept that it has its origin in the strong personality of its founderâ and that it âcould not be explained if it were not based on a personality powerful enough to give it the necessary impetus and to have marked it with its essential features which will persist throughout all history.â 25 What Lamotte means by âwill persist throughout all historyâ seems to be clarified somewhat in his 1949 âLa critique dâinterprĂ©tation dans le bouddhisme,â where he rejects the notion that later Buddhist doctrine diverged from the teaching of the Buddha and states that he is âof the opinion that the Buddhist Doctrine evolved along the lines which its discoverer had unconsciously traced [inconsciemment tracĂ©e] for it.â 26 For Lamotte, the relationship between the Buddha and Buddhism is fundamentally metaphysical in nature, with the mind and personality of the former serving as a mirror of the entire history of the latter. Lamotteâs assertion of this relationship seems to have been his only justification for presenting the Buddha as historical.
Although AndrĂ© Bareau was an equally strong believer in the Buddhaâs historicity, he also failed to add anything to the old arguments. In his 1966 âLe Bouddhisme indien,â he notes the views of Oldenberg, Wilson, Senart, and Kern, and states merely that ânowadays, however, the most widespread opinion, founded on a greater knowledge of philological and archaeological sources, admits that there really was a man to whom one must attribute the founding of Buddhism, a man the principal features of whose life and personality can be found through a thorough criticism of the dataâ (17). We thus again see Rhys Davidsâ old ad populum argument. Though Bareau states that current opinion is based on âa greater knowledge of the philological and archaeological sources,â in his own voluminous work on the matter he himself suggests that only a few minor details, such as the name Gautama, the names of a few of the Buddhaâs disciples, and the Buddhaâs death at KuĆinagara are most likely historical, though he concludes that even these are not certain. 27
There is little in all of this to inspire confidence in the historian. To summarize the process as it played out in Western scholarship: Despite travelersâ and missionary reports that had been coming in for centuries, in the early nineteenth century very little was known, and leading scholars regarded the Buddhaâs historicity as an open question. Sustained academic engagement with the question of Buddhismâs origin began in the late 1820s with Hodgsonâs announcement that Nepalese Sanskrit texts trace the origin of Buddhism to a lineage of seven Buddhas and claim to preserve the teachings of the final Buddha, ĆÄkyamuni. Over the next several decades, scholars struggled to make historical sense of these basic facts. They spent the first two decades ruminating over the problem of the previous Buddhas, never so much solving it as giving it up in frustration. 28 Following the publication of Burnoufâs Introduction, they shifted their focus to the final Buddha and spent roughly four more decades proposing one answer or the other on the question of whether or not he was historical. Though the historical faction won out, the scholars involved never cited any relevant facts, or made any significant argument in support of their views. Burnouf cited no more than pious Nepali belief. Hardy cited nothing, and eventually abandoned the idea. Max MĂŒller treated Wilsonâs doubts as legitimate until he later rejected them without any explicit justification. Koeppen, early Oldenberg, and Lamotte relied on versions of the Great Man theory, according to which it is inconceivable that Buddhism could have arisen without a powerful founder. Rhys Davids, later Oldenberg, and Bareau relied on ad populem arguments, which are inherently fallacious. Though it is often thought that evidence for the Buddhaâs historicity was found in Hodgson and Burnoufâs Sanskrit or Rhys Davids and Oldenbergâs Pali texts, this is not the case. None of these scholars made arguments from evidence. Although Thomas, Lamotte, and Bareau were all strong advocates of the idea of the historical Buddha, they each concluded that no evidence could be identified. 29 In the decades since Lamotte and Bareau, scholars of early Buddhism have continued to presume the Buddhaâs historicity, without adding anything to the old attempts to establish it.
Some, no doubt, will wish to say that it is unreasonable to ask for proof beyond the testimony of Buddhist tradition. Erich Frauwallner once stated exasperatedly that âthose who refuse to give credence to the tradition until a diary kept by Ananda has been found, duly authenticated by the authorities of RÄjagáčha and VaiĆÄlÄ«, will have long to waitâ (1957: 310). The problem here is that it is not clear that the tradition itself envisioned the Buddha as an actual person. Early Buddhist authors make little effort to associate the Buddha with any specific human identity. Familiar narratives of the Buddhaâs life may seem to tell the story of a specific person, but these are only found in late, non-canonical texts. Early texts, such as the suttas of the Pali canon, say hardly anything about the Buddhaâs life, and identify him in only vague terms. Rather than a specific human teacher, he appears primarily as a generic, omniscient, supra-divine figure characterized primarily in terms of supernatural qualities. Indeed, although this fact is almost invariably obscured in scholarship, early texts fail to provide us with a proper name. Though we often hear that the Buddha was SiddhÄrtha Gautama of the ĆÄkya clan, the name SiddhÄrtha (and its variants, SarvÄrthasiddha, etc.) is not attested in any early source. We do not, for example, find it used as a name for the Buddha anywhere in the Pali canon. Linking the Buddha to the ĆÄkyas certainly seems to provide realistic historical texture, but as Wilson pointed out long ago, the ĆÄkyas are not mentioned in any early non-Buddhist source (1832a: 7-8, 1856: 247). Further, according to ancient tradition, the ĆÄkyas were annihilated prior to the Buddhaâs death, suggesting that Buddhist authors themselves may have been unaware of their existence. The entire clan could easily be entirely mythical. 30 This leaves only Gautama, which is not so much a name as an epithet identifying the Buddha as being associated with the Gautama gotra, one of eight ancient gotras, or lineages, recognized by Brahmanical tradition that are said to have descended from eight mythical ráčŁsis. Though it is often presented as the Buddhaâs surname, the term has a broader application than ĆÄkya. All the ĆÄkyas in Buddhist texts are Gautamas, and many others besides. Central figures in other Indian traditions, including the UpaniáčŁadic sage YÄjñavalkya; IndrabhĆ«ti, said to have been MahÄvÄ«raâs chief disciple; and the traditional founder of the NyÄya darĆana, are also identified as Gautamas. 31
Many, I suspect, have felt that it is unlikely that a religious tradition would claim to have a single founder - or re-establisher - contrary to fact, but religious traditions often do so, among other reasons, to be able to specify a coherent source for authority or revelation. Indeed, many, perhaps most, religious traditions that claim to have a single founder did not actually have one. Scholars tell us, for instance, that Bodhidharma was an actual person, but that he had no direct connection to the Chan tradition as we now know it; that the Confucian and Hasidic traditions had already come into existence before Confucius and the Baal Shem Tov; and that figures such as Abraham, Moses, and Laozi (Lao-tzu) simply never lived. Much as Wilson suggested was the case for Buddhism, the traditions associated with each of these figures were founded by multiple people whose roles were later either obscured or effaced. Most religious traditions with premodern origins do not preserve an actual memory of their initial formation. Since the actual processes tend to be complex, difficult to remember, and not particularly edifying, they tend to be overwritten with simpler, mythical accounts.
Focusing specifically on India, the Vedas, MahÄbhÄrata, and PurÄáčas are said to have been composed or compiled by VyÄsa and the RÄmÄyana is attributed to VÄlmÄ«ki, neither of whom is regarded as historical. The early UpaniáčŁads, like Buddhist sĆ«tras, take the form of realistic dialogues with great teachers, and in fact provide significantly more biographical information for several of them than the vastly larger corpus of Buddhist sĆ«tras provides for the Buddha. In a recent monograph, however, Brian Black suggests that the main figures, such as UddÄlaka Äruáči and YÄjñavalkya, first appeared in the BrÄhmaáčas âmerely as names that add authority to particular teachings,â and were later developed in the UpaniáčŁads into complex figures with distinct backgrounds, families, ideas, and personalities:
One of the striking features of the characters is that they are all portrayed as true-to-life individuals. This is not to say that the narratives are historically accurate, but rather that the characters are presented as human and that their actions take place in the human world. In this way, there is a realistic thrust to the narrative. The characters are mere mortals who do things that are quite ordinary, such as discuss and debate, exchange greetings and offer hospitality⊠In contrast to many of the tales in the BrÄhmaáčas that take place on a mythic time scale and record the actions of gods (devas) and celestial beings (gandharvas), the Upanishadic narratives are firmly rooted in everyday life (Black 2007: 20-21).
Contributing to the overall effect, the early Upanisads also seem clearly to be set in a time very close to the one in which they were composed. Rather than actual fact, the realistic dialogical scenarios found in Buddhist sƫtras may reflect no more than that these texts represent a similar genre. In ancient India, attributing the origin of family lineages, religious traditions, and texts to mythical figures was not only the norm, but the rule, with very few known exceptions predating the Common Era.
Although the idea that the Buddha cannot be considered a historical figure may seem radical, my argument is really a minor one. Though there has long been an industry devoted to the production of sensational claims about the Buddha, nothing about him has ever been established as fact, and the standard position in scholarship has long been that he is a figure about whom we know nothing. My only real suggestion is that we make the small shift from speaking of an unknown, contentless Buddha to accepting that we do not have grounds for speaking of a historical Buddha at all. Of course, it is possible that there was some single, actual person behind the nebulous âĆramaáča Gautamaâ of the early texts, but this is very far from necessarily the case, and even if such a person did exist, we have no idea who he was. There may similarly have been an actual person behind the mythical Agamemnon, Homer, or King Arthur; VyÄsa, VÄlmÄ«ki, KáčáčŁna, or RÄma, but this does not make it possible to identify them as historical. If we wish to present early Buddhism in a manner that accords with the standards of scientific, empirical inquiry, it is necessary to acknowledge that the Buddha belongs to this group.
References
- App, Urs. 2009. William Jonesâs Ancient Theology. Sino-Platonic Papers, No. 191. Philadelphia: Department of East Asian Languages and Civilizations, University of Pennsylvania.
- App, Urs. 2010. The Birth of Orientalism. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.
- Bareau, AndrĂ©. 1963-1995. Recherches sur la biographie du Buddha dans les SĂŒtrapiáčaka et les Vinayapiáčaka anciens. 3 vols. Paris: Ăcole française dâExtrĂȘme-Orient.
- Bareau, AndrĂ©. 1966. âLe bouddhisme indien.â In Les religions de lâInde III: Bouddhisme, JaĂŻnisme, religions archaĂŻques. Paris: Payot: 7-246.
- Bareau, AndrĂ©. 1974. âLa jeunesse de Buddha dans les SĆ«trapiáčaka et les Vinayapiáčaka anciens.â Bulletin de lâĂcole française dâExtrĂȘme-Orient 61: 199-274.
- Bareau, AndrĂ©. 1979. âLa composition et les Ă©tapes de la formation progressive du MahÄparinirvÄnasĆ«tra ancien.â Bulletin de lâĂcole française dâExtrĂȘmeOrient 66: 45-103.
- Bareau, AndrĂ©. 1981. âLe massacre des ĆÄkya: essai dâinterprĂ©tation.â Bulletin de lâĂcole française dâExtrĂȘme-Orient 69 (1): 45-73.
- Black, Brian. 2007. The Character of the Self in Ancient India: Priests, Kings, and Women in the Early UpaniáčŁads. Albany: SUNY.
- Boin-Webb, Sara, trans. 1985. âThe Assessment of Textual Interpretation in Buddhism.â Buddhist Studies Review 2 (1/2): 4-24. (Translation of Lamotte 1949.)
- Brough, John. 1953. The Early Brahmanical System of Gotra and Pravara: A Translation of the Gotra-pravara-mañjarÄ« of PuruáčŁottama-paáčÌita. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Buffetrille, Katia and Donald S. Lopez Jr., trans. 2010. Introduction to the History of Indian Buddhism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. (Translation of Burnouf 1844.)
- Burnouf, EugĂšne, trans. 1827. âSur la littĂ©rature du Tibet, extrait du n° VII du Quarterly Oriental Magazine, Calcutta 1826.â Journal Asiatique 10 (March): 129-146. (Translation of Wilson 1825b.)
- Burnouf, EugĂšne. 1833-1834. Review in three parts of The MahĂĄvansi, the RĂĄjĂĄ-ratnĂĄcari, and the RĂĄjĂĄ-vali, Forming the Sacred and Historical Books of Ceylon; also, a Collection of Tracts Illustrative of the Doctrines and Literature of Buddhism, ed. Edward Upham. Journal des Savants 1833 (Sept.): 549-563 (part 1), 1834 (Jan.): 17-33 (part 2), 1834 (Apr.): 193-206 (part 3).
- Burnouf, EugÚne. 1837. Review in two parts of Rémusat et al. 1836. Journal des Savants March: 160-176 (part 1), June: 350-366 (part 2).
- Burnouf, EugĂšne. 1844. Introduction Ă lâhistoire du buddhisme indien. Vol. 1. Paris.
- Burnouf, EugĂšne. 1891. Choix de lettres dâEugĂšne Burnouf 1825-1852, suivi dâune bibliographie. Edited by Laure Burnouf Delisle. Paris.
- Burnouf, EugĂšne and Christian Lassen. 1826. Essai sur le Pali, ou langue sacrĂ©e de la presquâile au-dela du Gange. Paris.
- Colebrooke, Henry Thomas. 1827. âOn the Philosophy of the Hindusâ (Part 4). Transactions of the Royal Asiatic Society of Great Britain and Ireland 1: 549-579.
- Coningham, R. A. E. et al. 2013. âThe earliest Buddhist shrine: Excavating the birthplace of the Buddha, Lumbini (Nepal).â Antiquity 87 (338): 1104-1123.
- Crawfurd, John. 1830. Journal of an Embassy from the Governor-General of India to the Courts of Siam and Cochin China. 2 vols. 2nd ed., London.
- Csoma de KĆrös, Alexander. 1834. âEpoch of the Death of Shakya, According to Different Authorities.â In A Grammar of the Tibetan Language, in English. Calcutta: 199-202.
- Csoma de KĆrös, Alexander. 1838. âNotices on the Different Systems of Buddhism, Extracted from the Tibetan Authorities.â Journal of the Asiatic Society of Bengal 7 (74): 142-147.
- Csoma de KĆrös, Alexander. 1839. âAnalysis of the Sher-chin - Pâhal-châhen -Dkon-sĂ©ks - Do-dĂ© - NyĂĄng-dĂĄs - and Gyut; Being the 2nd, 3rd,4th, 5th, 6th, and 7th Divisions of the Tibetan Work, Entitled the Kah-gyur.â Asiatic Researches 20 (2): 393-552.
- Dundas, Paul. (1992) 2002. The Jains. 2nd ed., London: Routledge.
- Edgerton, Franklin. 1959. âDid the Buddha Have a System of Metaphysics?â Journal of the American Oriental Society 79 (2): 81-85.
- Forbes, Jonathan. 1836. âNotes on the Buddhas from Ceylonese Authorities, with an Attempt to Fix the Dates of the Appearance of the Last Four; Being Those of the MahĂĄ Bhadra Kalpa, (or Present Age).â Journal of the Asiatic Society of Bengal 5 (54): 321-330.
- Forbes, Jonathan. 1840. Eleven Years in Ceylon. Comprising Sketches of the Field Sports and Natural History of That Colony, and an Account of Its History and Antiquities. 2 vols. London.
- Franke, R. Otto. 1914. âDie dogmatische Buddha nach dem DÄ«ghanikÄya.â Wiener Zeitschrift fĂŒr die Kunde des Morgenlandes 28: 331-355.
- Franke, R. Otto. 1915/1916. âĂber die angeblichen Knochenreliqiuen des Buddha Gotama.â Ostasiatische Zeitschrift 4: 1-11.
- Franke, R. Otto. 1915-1917. âDie Buddhalehre in ihrer erreichbar-Ă€ltesten Gestalt (im DÄ«ghanikÄya).â Zeitschrift der Deutschen MorgenlĂ€ndischen Gesellschaft 69: 455-490 (part 1), 71: 50-98 (part 2).
- Frauwallner, Erich. 1957. âThe Historical Data We Possess on the Person and the Doctrine of the Buddha.â East and West 7 (4): 309-312.
- Glasenapp, Helmuth von. 1959. âNachwort.â In Hermann Oldenberg, Buddha: Sein Leben, seine Lehre, seine Gemeinde. 13th ed., Stuttgart: Cotta: 453-519.
- Gogerly, Daniel J. 1847. âNotes on Buddhism.â In Abbe le Grand, trans., History of Ceylon, Presented by Captain John Ribeyro to the King of Portugal, in 1685. Colombo: 264-273.
- Gombrich, Richard. 2009. What the Buddha Thought. London: Equinox.
- Hardy, R. Spence. 1850. Eastern Monachism: An Account of the Origin, Laws, Discipline, Sacred Writings, Mysterious Rites, Religious Ceremonies, and Present Circumstances of the Order of Mendicants Founded by GĂłtama Budha. London.
- Hardy, R. Spence. 1853. A Manual of Budhism, in Its Modern Development. London.
- Hardy, R. Spence. 1863. The Sacred Books of the Buddhists Compared With History and Modern Science. Colombo.
- Hardy, R. Spence. 1866. The Legends and Theories of the Buddhists, Compared with History and Science: With Introductory Notices of the Life and System of Gotama Buddha. London.
- Hardy, R. Spence. 1874. Christianity and Buddhism Compared. Colombo.
- Harris, Elizabeth J. 2006. TheravÄda Buddhism and the British Encounter: Religious, Missionary and Colonial Experience in Nineteenth-century Sri Lanka. London: Routledge.
- HinĂŒber, Oskar von. 1991. âLinguistic Considerations on the Date of the Buddha.â In Heinz Bechert, ed., The Dating of the Historical Buddha/Die Datierung des historischen Buddha. Part 1. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht: 183-193.
- HinĂŒber, Oskar von and Peter Skilling. 2013. âTwo Buddhist Inscriptions from Deorkothar (Dist. Rewa, Madhya Pradesh).â Annual Report of The International Research Institute for Advanced Buddhology at Soka University 16: 13-26.
- Hodgson, Brian Houghton. 1828. âNotices of the Languages, Literature, and Religion of the Bauddhas of Nepal and Bhot.â Asiatic Researches 16: 409-449.
- Hodgson, Brian Houghton. 1841. Illustrations of the Literature and Religion of the Buddhists. Serampore.
- Hodgson, Brian Houghton. 1874. âOn the Languages, Literature, and Religion of Nepaul and Tibet.â In Essays on the Languages, Literature, and Religion of NepĂĄl and Tibet: Together with Further Papers on the Geography, Ethnology, and Commerce of Those Countries. Part 1. London: 1-35.
- Hoey, William, trans. 1882. Buddha: His Life, His Doctrine, His Order. London/ Edinburgh. (Translation of Oldenberg 1881.)
- Jones, William. 1788. âThe Third Anniversary Discourse.â Asiatick Researches 1: 343-355.
- Kaempfer, Engelbert. 1727. The History of Japan, Giving an Account of the Ancient and Present State and Government of That Empire ⊠Together with a Description of the Kingdom of Siam. Translated by J. G. Scheuchzer. 2 vols. London.
- Kern, Hendrik. 1901-1903. Histoire du bouddhisme dans lâInde. Translated by GĂ©dĂ©on Huet. 2 vols. Paris: Ernest Leroux. (Originally published in Dutch in 1882-1884 as Geschiedenis van het Buddhisme in IndiĂ«.)
- Kern, Hendrik. 1896. Manual of Indian Buddhism. Strasburg.
- Klaproth, Julius. 1823. Asia Polyglotta. Paris.
- Knighton, William. 1845. The History of Ceylon from the Earliest Period to the Present Time. London/Edinburgh.
- Koeppen, Carl Friedrich. 1857-1859. Die Religion des Buddha. 2 vols. Berlin.
- [Laidly, John W.] Anonymous, trans. 1848. The Pilgrimage of Fa Hian; from the French Edition of the Foe Koue Ki of MM. Remusat, Klaproth, and Landresse. Calcutta (Translation of Rémusat et al. 1836.)
- Lamotte, Ătienne, trans. 1944-1980. Le traitĂ© de la grande vertu de sagesse de NÄgÄrjuna (MahÄprajñÄpÄramitÄĆÄstra). 5 vols. Louvain: UniversitĂ© de Louvain, Institut orientaliste. (Vols. 1-2 repr. 1981.)
- Lamotte, Ătienne. 1947. âLa lĂ©gende du Buddha.â Revue de lâhistoire des religions 134(1 / 3): 37-71.
- Lamotte, Ătienne. 1949. âLa critique dâinterprĂ©tation dans le bouddhisme.â Annuaire de lâInstitut de philologie et dâhistoire orientales et slaves 9: 341-361.
- Lamotte, Ătienne. 1958. Histoire du bouddhisme indien: des origines Ă lâĂšre Ćaka. Louvain: Publications universitaires, Institut orientaliste.
- Lopez, Donald S. Jr. 2013. From Stone to Flesh: A Short History of the Buddha. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
- Monier-Williams, Monier. 1889. Buddhism, in Its Connexion with BrÄhmanism and HindĆ«ism and in Its Contrast with Christianity. London.
- MĂŒller, Max. 1857. Buddhism and Buddhist Pilgrims. A Review of M. Stanislas Julienâs âVoyages des PĂȘlerins Bouddhistes.â London/Edinburgh/Paris.
- MĂŒller, Max. (1862) 1867. âBuddhism.â Repr. in Chips from a German Workshop. Vol. 1. London: 181-234.
- Obeyesekere, Gananath. 1997. âTaking the Myth Seriously: The Buddha and the Enlightenment.â In Petra Kieffer-PĂŒlz and Jens-Uwe Hartmann, eds., BauddhavidyÄsudhÄkarah: Studies in Honour of Heinz Bechert on the Occasion of His 65th Birthday. Swisttal-Odendorf: Indica et Tibetica: 473-482.
- Oldenberg, Hermann. 1881. Buddha: Sein Leben, seine Lehre, seine Gemeinde. Berlin.
- Oldenberg, Hermann. 1890. Buddha: Sein Leben, seine Lehre, seine Gemeinde. 2nd ed., Berlin.
- Oldenberg, Hermann. 1897. Buddha: Sein Leben, seine Lehre, seine Gemeinde. 3rd$ enlarged ed., Berlin.
- Oldenberg, Hermann. 1903. Buddha: Sein Leben, seine Lehre, seine Gemeinde. 4th ed., Stuttgart/Berlin: J.G. Cotta.
- Oldenberg, Hermann. 1906. Buddha: Sein Leben, seine Lehre, seine Gemeinde. 5th ed., Stuttgart/Berlin: J.G. Cotta.
- Oldenberg, Hermann. 1914. Buddha: Sein Leben, seine Lehre, seine Gemeinde. 6th ed., Stuttgart: J.G. Cotta.
- Oldenberg, Hermann. 1920. Buddha: Sein Leben, seine Lehre, seine Gemeinde. 7th ed., Stuttgart: J.G. Cotta.
- RĂ©musat, Jean-Pierre Abel-. 1819. âNote sur quelques Ă©pithĂštes descriptives de Bouddha.â Journal des Savans October: 625-633.
- RĂ©musat, Jean-Pierre Abel-. 1821. âSur la succession des trente-trois premiers patriarches de la religion de Bouddha.â Journal des Savans January: 6-15.
- RĂ©musat, Jean-Pierre Abel-. 1831a. âEssai sur la cosmographie et la cosmogonie des Bouddhistes, dâaprĂšs les auteurs chinoisâ (Part 3). Journal des Savans December: 716-731.
- RĂ©musat, Jean-Pierre Abel-. 1831b. âObservations sur lâouvrage de M. Schmidt, intitulĂ© Histoire des Mongols orientauxâ (Part 1). Journal Asiatique, 2nd ser., 8: 507-532.
- RĂ©musat, Jean-Pierre Abel-. 1831c. âObservations sur trois MĂ©moires de M. Deguignes insĂ©rĂ©s dans le tome XL de la Collection de lâAcadĂ©mie des
- Inscriptions et Belles-Lettres, et relatifs Ă la religion samanĂ©enne.â Journal Asiatique, 2nd ser., 7: 241-301.
- RĂ©musat, Jean-Pierre Abel-. 1843a. âAnalyse de lâhistoire des Mongols de Sanang-Setsen.â In MĂ©langes posthumes dâhistoire et de littĂ©rature orientales. Paris: 373-458.
- RĂ©musat, Jean-Pierre Abel-. 1843b. âObservations sur les sectes religieuses des Hindous.â In MĂ©langes posthumes dâhistoire et de littĂ©rature orientales. Paris: 132-159.
- RĂ©musat, Jean-Pierre Abel-, Julius Heinrich Klaproth, and Ernest Augustin Xavier Clerc de Landresse, trans. 1836. FoĂ« KouĂ« Ki, ou Relation des royaumes bouddhiques, voyage dans la Tartarie, dans lâAfghanistan et dans lâInde, exĂ©cutĂ©, Ă la fin du IVe siĂšcle, par ChĂœ FĂą Hian. Paris.
- Rhys Davids, T. W. n.d. [1877]. Buddhism: Being a Sketch of the Life and Teachings of Gautama, The Buddha. London/New York.
- Rhys Davids, T. W. 1878. âBuddhism.â In Encyclopoedia Britannica. 9th ed., vol. 4. New York: s.v.
- Rhys Davids, T. W. 1902. âRecent Discoveries Concerning the Buddha: The Identification of his Birthplace and One of the Burial-places of His Ashes.â The Century Magazine 63 (6): 837-843.
- Salomon, Richard and Joseph Marino. 2014. âObservations on the Deorkothar Inscriptions and Their Significance for the Evaluation of Buddhist Historical Traditions.â Annual Report of The International Research Institute for Advanced Buddhology at Soka University 17: 27-39.
- Schmidt, I. J. 1830. âUeber einige Grundlehren des Buddhaismus.â MĂ©moires de lâAcadĂ©mie impĂ©riale des sciences de St.-PĂ©tersbourg, ser. 6, Sciences politiques, histoire et philologie 1 (2): 89-120 (part 1), (3): 221-262 (part 2).
- Schmidt, I. J. 1833. âUeber die tausend Buddhas einer Weltperiode der Einwohnung oder gleichmĂ€ssigen Dauer.â MĂ©moires de lâAcadĂ©mie impĂ©riale des sciences de St.-PĂ©tersbourg, ser. 6, Sciences politiques, histoire et philologie 2 (1): 41-86.
- Senart, Ămile. (1873-1875) 1875. Essai sur la lĂ©gende du Buddha, son caractĂšre et ses origines. Extrait du Journal Asiatique (AnnĂ©es 1873-1875). Paris.
- Senart, Ămile. 1882. Essai sur la lĂ©gende du Buddha: son caractĂšre et ses origines. 2nd rev. ed., Paris.
- Senart, Ămile. 1907. Origines bouddhiques. Paris.
- Silk, Jonathan A. 1994. âThe Victorian Creation of Buddhism.â Review of The British Discovery of Buddhism, by Philip C. Almond. Journal of Indian Philosophy 22 (2): 171-196.
- Silk, Jonathan A. 2012. âKern and the Study of Indian Buddhism, with a Speculative Note on the Ceylonese Dhammarucikas.â Journal of the Pali Text Society 31: 125-154.
- Thomas, Edward J. 1927. The Life of Buddha as Legend and History. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.
- Turnour, George, trans. 1836. The First Twenty Chapters of the Mahawanso: And a Prefatory Essay on Pali Buddhistical Literature Originally Published as an Introduction to the above Mentioned Portion of the Mahawanso and to the Epitome of the History of Ceylon, and the Historical Inscriptions, Printed in the Ceylon Almanacs of 1833 and 1834. [Sri Jayawardenepura Kotte], Sri Lanka.
- Turnour, George. 1838. âAn Examination of the PĂĄlĂ Buddhistical Annals, No. 3.â Journal of the Asiatic Society of Bengal 7 (80): 686-701.
- Turnour, George, trans. 1840. âTranslation of Inscriptions, with an Introduction.â In Forbes 1840: 2.324-356.
- Walters, Jonathan S. 1998. Finding Buddhists in Global History. Washington, D.C.: American Historical Association.
- Webb-Boin, Sara, trans. 1988. History of Indian Buddhism: From the Origins to the Saka Era. Louvain-la-Neuve: Institut orientaliste, Université catholique de Louvain. (Translation of Lamotte 1958.)
- Williams, Paul. (2000) 2002. Buddhist Thought: A Complete Introduction to the Indian Tradition. With Anthony Tribe. London: Routledge.
- Wilson, Horace Hayman. 1819. A Dictionary, Sanscrit and English: Translated, Amended and Enlarged, from an Original Compilation Prepared by Learned Natives for the College of Fort William. Calcutta.
- Wilson, Horace Hayman. 1825a. âAn Essay on the Hindu History of Cashmir.â Asiatic Researches 15: 1-119.
- [Wilson, Horace Hayman] Anonymous. 1825b. âOn the Literature and Language of ThĂŻbet, Ăra of Buddha, and Progress of the Bauddha Religion.â Quarterly Oriental Magazine, Review, and Register 4 (7): 96-113.
- Wilson, Horace Hayman. 1828. âNotice of Three Tracts Received from Nepal.â Asiatic Researches 16: 450-478.
- Wilson, Horace Hayman. 1832a. âAbstract of the Contents of the Dul-vĂĄ, or First Portion of the KĂĄh-gyur, from the Analysis of Mr. Alexander Csoma de Körös.â Journal of the Asiatic Society of Bengal 1 (1): 1-8.
- Wilson, Horace Hayman. 1832b. âSketch of the Religious Sects of the Hindusâ (Part 2). Asiatic Researches 17: 169-313.
- Wilson, Horace Hayman. 1856. âOn Buddha and Buddhism.â Journal of the Royal Asiatic Society of Great Britain & Ireland 16: 229-265.
Footnotes
-
This paper was initially presented at the XVII-th IABS Congress in Vienna in 2014. â©
-
Kaempfer 1727: 1.35-39, RĂ©musat 1819; cf. Jones 1788: 352-353, Lopez 2013: 133-139,151-157. â©
-
Klaproth 1823: 144 (this passage occurs in the âLeben des Buddâaâ chapter appended to the end of the text, paginated separately), Jones 1788: 350; cf. Lopez 2013: 151-152, 179 . â©
-
Wilson 1825a: 83-84, 1825b: 106-110. For the identification of Wilson as the author of 1825b, published anonymously, see Wilson 1856: 247. EugĂšne Burnouf (1827) translated this article into French for the Journal Asiatique. See also Crawfurd (1830: 2.81-85), where the author transcribes notes he received from Wilson on this issue. Cf. Lopez 2013: 216. On the two-Buddha theory in general, see App 2009: 56-58, Lopez 2013: 143-152. â©
-
RĂ©musat 1819: 629; see also 631. â©
-
Hodgson 1828. Hodgson states that his 1828 paper was initially written in 1825 (1841: preface). For 1822 as the date of Hodgsonâs discovery, see Burnouf 1844: 578. â©
-
Hodgson 1828: 422, 443-445, 447. I have normalized the spelling of the Buddhasâ names. â©
-
Hodgson 1828: 422, 445, his emphasis. Hodgsonâs views changed over the years in response to the work of other scholars. In a revised version of his 1828 article published in 1841, he changed his statement that âit has not occurred to me at present to doubt the historical existence of SĂĄkyaâs six predecessorsâ to âit has frequently occurred to me to doubt the historical existence of SĂĄkyaâs six predecessorsâ (1841: 46). He also parenthetically adds âif not also the first and onlyâ to his assertion that ĆÄkyamuni was the last of the seven Buddhas (1841: 17). In an 1874 version of the article, he states, âI think it may be safely asserted that all of the so-called mortal Buddhas save the last are mythological shadows,â and that âSĂĄkya Sinha ⊠must be concluded to be the founder of this creedâ (1874: 12, 32). â©
-
RĂ©musat 1831c: 264, 1843b: 153. â©
-
RĂ©musat et al. 1836: 187, n. 35, trans. in Laidlay 1848: 179, n. 35; cf. RĂ©musat et al. 1836: 194-197, n. 8, Laidlay 1848: 185-187, n. 4. RĂ©musat also addresses the seven Buddhas, e.g., in 1831a, 1831b: 522-523, and 1843a: 389-390. â©
-
Turnour 1836: 1-lii, his emphasis. Turnour states that as far as he is aware this âimportant pointâ has ânot been noticed by any other writerâ (1836: 1). On the importance of Turnourâs insight, see also Laidlay 1848: 187-188. â©
-
See also Forbes 1840: 2.195-196, 203, where the author presents the same dates. â©
-
Turnour 1840: 325. Belief, or at least interest, in the previous Buddhas persisted for some time among British scholars in Sri Lanka. See, e.g., Knighton 1845: 66-67, Gogerly 1847: 264-265, Hardy 1853: 86-88, 1863: 140-142, 1866: 198-201. See also note 27. Alexander Csoma de KĆrös and Isaak Jacob Schmidt also addressed the previous Buddhas, though they do not seem to have made a significant contribution to the discussion. See, e.g., Schmidt 1830: 1.105-110, 2.242-243 and 1833 and Csoma de KĆrös 1838: 143, 1839: 414-415. For Csomaâs views, see also Csoma de KĆrös 1834. â©
-
Burnouf 1844: 43-44, trans. in Buffetrille and Lopez 2010: 91-92. Burnouf had already addressed the question of the historical Buddha or Buddhas in previous publications. In his Essai sur le Pali, co-authored with Christian Lassen, he argued in support of a version of the two-Buddha theory. Following RĂ©musat 1821, he accepted a date of 950 for the death of ĆÄkyamuni, but suggested that the Buddha known to Pali sources was a different figure who died in 543 (Burnouf and Lassen 1826: 49-52; cf. Burnouf 1827: 143-144, n. 1). He abandoned this theory, and RĂ©musatâs date of 950, in later publications (1833-1834: 2.22-23, 3.202-203; 1837: 2.356). See also the following note. â©
-
Burnouf presented this idea already in his review of Edward Uphamâs The MahĂĄvansi (1833-1834: 3.202-203; but cf. 2.22), which was published prior to RĂ©musatâs translation of the Fo guo ji. He was in contact with RĂ©musat until the time of his death, however, and almost surely saw RĂ©musatâs translation before it was published, mentioning its progress in personal letters in 1827 and 1834 (Burnouf 1891: 55, 183). As we have seen, Burnouf attributes the idea to âcapable critics.â Since RĂ©musat similarly attributes the idea to âgeneral belief,â however, there is some mystery as to who first advocated it. â©
-
Wilson and Burnouf knew and greatly admired each other. Burnouf met and visited Wilson at his home in 1835. In letters to his wife, he describes Wilson in very lofty terms, going so far as to describe himself as being âvisibly movedâ when he first entered Wilsonâs study to meet him (Burnouf 1891: 197). In an 1850 letter to Wilson, he twice addresses him as âillustre maĂźtre,â and writes that no one in Europe can âpronounce the name of India without having consulted youâ (Burnouf 1891: 417). For Burnoufâs description of a rather disastrous dinner at Wilsonâs house in Oxford, however, see Burnouf 1891: 204-208. Of Burnouf, Wilson writes that he âaccomplished more than any other scholar, more than it would seem possible for any human ability and industry to have achieved, [and] it is to be deeply and for ever regretted that his life was not spared to have effected all he had intendedâ (Wilson 1856: 229). â©
-
Hardy 1866: xiii, 71-73; cf. 1863: 50-52. â©
-
Hardy 1874: 35-36; cf. Harris 2006: 68. â©
-
For Senartâs views, see also Senart 1882, 1907. Jonathan Silk suggests that Kernâs Geschiedenis was originally published in 1881 and 1883 (2012: 126 and n. 3). For an interesting, more recent attempt to read the legend of the Buddha as myth, see Obeyesekere 1997. â©
-
Rhys Davids 1878: 425; cf. 1877: 16-17. â©
-
In a 1902 article, Rhys Davids treats the Pali MahÄparinibbÄnasutta as somehow constituting evidence for the Buddhaâs historicity and writes, âBut this book had become unknown in India ⊠The few contemptuous references to the great reformer, found by the discoveries of Sanskrit literature in the medieval writings of the priests, are so vague that the eminent Sanskritist Horace Hayman Wilson believed him to be nothing more real than a sun-mythâ (1902: 837). Rhys Davids would thus seem to endorse the view that the Buddhaâs historicity had not yet been discovered at the time Wilson wrote in the 1850s. Wilson in fact never suggested that the Buddha was a sun-myth; Rhys Davids conflates his view with those of Senart and Kern. â©
-
Oldenberg 1881: 73, 75, trans. in Hoey 1882: 72, 74. â©
-
Oldenberg 1903, 1906, 1914, 1920. On the revision history of Oldenbergâs text, see Edgerton 1959: 81, von Glasenapp 1959: 457-458. â©
-
Thomas 1927: 233-234, trans. of Franke 1915-1917: 1.455. For other publications on this issue by Franke, see the references in Thomas 1927: 234-235, n. 4 and also Franke 1914, 1915/1916. â©
-
Lamotte 1958: 16, 707, trans. in Webb-Boin 1988: 15, 639. â©
-
Lamotte 1949: 361, trans. in Boin-Webb 1985: 20. â©
-
For Bareauâs conclusions, see primarily 1963-1995: 1.379-385, 1974, 1979. â©
-
Perhaps the most insightful comment on the matter is Kernâs: âIt is a common opinion among European savans that the Buddhas preceding ĆÄkyamuni are mythical, the latter alone being historical. That theory, whether true or false, is entirely opposed to the fixed dogma of historical Buddhism. Of course, we may surmise that in original Buddhism the matter stood otherwise. Such a supposition is allowable, provided we do not confound an hypothesis of our own making with the facts of sober historyâ (1896: 64, his emphasis). â©
-
For more recent comments on the lack of factual evidence for the Buddha, see, e.g., Silk 1994: 183, Walters 1998: 23-24, Williams (2000) 2002: 25, Christian Wedemeyer quoted in Gombrich 2009: 193-194, App 2010: 136. Some have suggested that recent archaeological discoveries may be relevant to the question of the historical Buddha. Coningham et al. present evidence of what seems to have been a tree shrine, dating to some time between the ninth and sixth centuries, found beneath the AĆokan layer at LumbinÄ«. Presuming that the Buddha must have lived before the creation of the shrine, the authors suggest that it may represent âthe first archaeological evidence for the date of the Buddhaâ (2013: 1108-1109, 1119). As several scholars have pointed out in online forums, however, there seems to be nothing to connect the pre-AĆokan shrine to Buddhism. It thus seems more likely that Buddhists appropriated an originally non-Buddhist shrine for the site of the Buddhaâs birth. Skilling and von HinĂŒber (2013) and Salomon and Marino (2014) present two recently discovered pillar inscriptions from Madhya Pradesh, apparently dating to the second century B.C.E., that record monastic lineages going back to the Buddha. As Salomon and Marino point out, however, there is no way to know the extent to which these lineages may have been fabricated (2014: 33). Because they represent assertions of legitimacy and prestige, unsubstantiated lineage claims cannot be treated as historical evidence, as has clearly been shown, e.g., by studies of early Chan lineages. Though Richard Gombrich scornfully rejects skepticism about the Buddhaâs historicity in his What the Buddha Thought, surely the boldest recent publication on the matter, he does not present any clear argument to defend it (2009: 194). â©
-
On this story, see mainly Bareau 1974: 268-69 and 1981. See also Lamotte 19441980: 1.508-509, n. 1.5° for a list of references to traditional accounts. â©
-
On Gautama as a gotra name, see, e.g., Burnouf 1844: 155, Oldenberg 1881: 420421, Thomas 1927: 22-23, Brough 1953: 5-6 and 5, n. 3. Oskar von HinĂŒber has also suggested that MÄyÄ, the traditional name for the Buddhaâs mother, was derived from what was originally simply the word mÄtÄ, âmother.â He also points out that âthe designation of his stepmother mahÄpajÄpati, i.e. mahÄpajÄvati, Gotami can hardly be considered to be an individual nameâ (1991: 187). Paul Dundas points out that the Jain IsibhÄsiyÄim depicts ĆÄriputra and MahÄkÄĆyapa as authoritative teachers, which suggests that they may have been recognized figures before being incorporated into Buddhist texts as disciples of the Buddha ([1992] 2002: 17-19). â©